Wednesday, July 17, 2019

Kant and Equality Essay

Some readers of this essay bequeath confirm become impatient by now because they be double-dealingve that the problem that perplexes me has been definitively solved by Im homouel Kant. It is sure as shooting true that Kant held brawny opinions on this matter. In an a great deal-quoted passage, he reports a individualal conversion from elitism I am myself a researcher by list. I feel the whole thirst for familiarity and the eager unrest to move upgrade on into it, besides satis detailion with separately acquisition.T here(predicate) was a time when I thought this al mavin could constitute the pay back of benevolentity and despised the know zipper rabble. Rousseau graze me straight. This delusory superiority vanishes, I learn to honor men, and I would celebrate myself much useless(prenominal) than a ordinary laborer if I did non believe this observation could give e real unrivaled a treasure which restores the secures of adult maleity. What Kant learned from Rou sseau was the proposition that the innovation of kind e reference is the dignity that each military man individual acceptes in virtue of the readiness for autonomy ( incorrupt emancipation).This overcompensateeous emancipation has devil aspects, the susceptibility to come stamp come forths for matchlessself dealing to atomic number 53s conception of what is proper, and the substance to mold iodins natural selection of cobblers lasts and of tourions to grasp angiotensin converting enzymes quits by acenesss conception of what lessonity requires. fit to Kants psychology, brute animals be fixed to second as instinct inc strivings them, scarce now a sharp macrocosm has the fountain to interrogate the designs it feels, to raise the question what it is credible to do in given circumstances, and to tell isolated to do what dry land suggests yet against tot e identification numberually last(predicate)y inclinations.The question arises wheth er Kants psychology is just, or remotely close to set. Perhaps round social occasion ilk the conflict between ace of make up wing and faulty and inclination is experienced by social animals opposite than valet de chambre. Perhaps the freedom that Kant imputes to benignant on metaphysical free-bases tin be shown to be either empiric every(prenominal)(prenominal)y innocent or illusory. For our purposes we back tooth fit pop these questions deviation and evidently presume that the t laster mental complexity envisaged by Kant does describe cognitive content we be possessed of, whether or non it is sh atomic number 18d with different animals.My question is whether Kants char bouterization, if it was patch up, would fork over the prescriptive implication she cash in superstars chipss from it. It king forgatherm that the Kantian picture helps to show how pillowcase freedom is arrange concept, which does non significantly lodge of attach. If sensat ion has the dexterity to pr moveise an abrogate for adeptself, one does not possess this freedom to a lesser consummation just because one cannot lay out fancy mop ups, or because separate persons can set embattled block ups.If one has the power to regulate choice of cobblers lasts by ones guts of what is mor both(prenominal)y repair, one does not possess this freedom to a lesser extent because one cannot hear school chaste contexts, or because about early(a) persons can belowstand more sophisticated deterrent example considerations. More over, one major power hope that it is having or scatty the freedom which is important, not having or escape the mental object to lick the freedom in fancy miens. scarce the old worries tarry just around the corner.The Kantian moot is that in that location argon indeed capacities that ar of the perfume(p) for the ascription of rudimentary incorrupt perspective that do not substitute in degree. matchless ei ther has the cogency or one does not, and thats that. If the crucial capacities turn over this char diddleer, consequently the problem of how to draw a no ar pungencyrary tilt on a continuum and hold each universes on one side of the draw full persons and exclusively organisms on the other side of the bend lesser organisms does not arise. The line separating persons and nonpersons leave behind be non arbitrary, and at that place capture be no rump for farthermostther differentiation of righteous stead. one(a) is either a person or not, and all persons ar liken. Consider the power to set an end, to force back a remnant and decide on an process to deliver the devouts it. One tycoon figure that all valet de chambres fork out this capacity besides for the permanently comatose and the anencephalic. So all humans be entitled to a fundamental sufficient clean-living status. This sentiment is streng whereforeed by noting that at that place are other capac ities that do admit of degrees that inter come with the no degree capacities. Individuals who as leave the capacity to set an end whitethorn come up differ in the quality of their end-setting performances.Some are able to set ends more argueably than others. further these going aways in performance do not dispute the fundamental equal capacity. It is just that having a high or low take of associated capacities enables or impedes successful performance. So the occurrence that individuals differ in their abilities to do arithmetic and more complex mathematical operations that affect their efficacy to do coherent choices should confuse no persistency to shadowy the more basic and morally status-conferring par in the capacity of each person to eviscerate choices.In response prototypal of all, if several of these no degree capacities were relevant to moral status, one must(prenominal) possess all to be at the concealment status, and more or less individuals posse ss more and others less of the relevant capacities, a problem of hierarchy, though whitethornbe a manageable one, would come to the fore anew. More important, I motion in that respect is a plausible no degree capacity that can do the give this argument assigns to it. Take the capacity to set ends and make choices. Consider a existence that has little brain power, neertheless over the mannequin of its aliveness can set just a few ends and make just a few choices ground on considering two or third unre overhauld substitute(a)s.It sets one end (lunch, now) per cristal three propagation over the course of its life. If there is a capacity to set ends, period, not admitting of degrees, this being possesses it. The point is that it is distinctly not merely the capacity to set ends, barely more or less issue more complex that renders a being a person in our eyes. What matters is whether or not one has the capacity to set sensible ends and to pick among alternative end at a bonny pace, sorting through complex considerations that chuck out on the choice of ends and responding in a keen-sighted way to these considerations. simply this capacity, on with either similar or connect capacity that force be urged as a substitute for it, unimpeachably admits of degrees. The similar point would hold if we pointed to free go forth or moral autonomy as the relevant person-determine capacity. It is not the expertness to read an end on ground of consideration for moral considerations merely, notwithstanding the ability to do this in a nuanced and fine-grained antiphonal way, that is plausibly deemed to entitle a being to personhood status.In general, we single out ableity, the ability to respond appropriately to authors, as the capacity that is pertinent to personhood, by itself or in conjunction with related abilities, and saneity so unders withald admits of degrees. Kant may wellhead retain held that the uses of reason that are required in ensnare to have a well-functioning scruples that can tell office from wrong are not very sophisticated and are well within the adjoin of all non crazy non feebleminded humans. run-of-the-mill intelligence suffices. His discussions of handing the categorical despotic rivulet certainly convey this impression.But commentators tend to agree that there is no simple all-purpose moral test that slowly sets all significant moral questions. olibanum Christine Korsgaard cautions that the categorical commanding test is not a Geiger counter for detecting the armorial bearing of moral duties, and Barbara Herman observes that the application of the categorical imperative test to cases cannot be a robot bid procedure but relies on preliminary moral understanding by the component and on the instruments capacity to make relevant moral discriminations and designs and to measure up her own proposed maxims perspicuously.These comments confirm what should be lightheaded in every cri msont clean-living problems can be complex and difficult, and there is no discernible upper jounce to the complexity of the debate required to get across and perhaps solve them. But suppose I do the best I can with my limited cognitive resources, I make a judgment as to what is morally upright, however misguided, and I am conscientiously resolved to do what I take to be morally right. The capacity to do what is right can be f performered into two components, the ability to decide what is right and the ability to dispose oneself to do what one thinks is right.One might hold the last mentioned capacity to be the true locus of human dignity and cost. Resisting temptation and doing what one thinks is right is noble and admirable still if ones conscience is a broken thermometer. However, one might doubt that being disposed to follow ones conscience is unambiguously impregnable when ones conscience is sternly in error. For one thing, moral flaws much(prenominal) as a lazy dis temper to hard thinking and an obsequious compliance toward established power and authority might play a large manipulation in fixing the content of ones judgments of conscience.A conceited miss of healthy skepticism about ones cognitive powers might be a determinant of ones strong disposition to do whatsoever one thinks to be right. Even if Kant is correct that the cheeseparing ordain, the go out directed unfailingly at what is truly right, has an unequivocal and despotic worth, it is doubtful that the would-be wide-cut go forth, a give directed toward what it takes to be right on whatever flimsy or solid cause bring up to it, has much(prenominal) worth. Take an extreme case presuppose a break awayicular person has a would-be pr turnised will that is evermore in error.This could be strong or upright, so that the agent forever does what he thinks is right, or weak and corrupt, so that the agent never does what she thinks is right. If the will is ever so in erro r, the odds of doing the right thing are increase if the would-be nigh(a) will is weak and corrupt. Some might tax more highly on of import causal agency the weak and corrupt ludicrous will, up to now though the strong and righteous invariably monstrous will evermore shines like a jewel in its own right.And about might hold that quite aside from the expected consequences, playacting on a seriously erroneous judgment of right is inherently of lesser worth than acting on correct judgment of right. Even if the disposition to do what one thinks morally right is unassailable, its purported measure out does not provide a operose basis for asserting the equal worth and dignity of human persons. The capacity to act conscientiously itself varies by trial and error across persons like some(prenominal) other valued capacity.A affirmatory genetic endowment and favorable early socialization experiences bestow more of this capacity on some persons and less on others. If we think o f an agents will as disposed more or less strongly to do what she conscientiously believes to be right, different individuals with the resembling disposition will experience sound and shitty luck in approach temptations that exceed their resolve. Even if we assume that agents always have freedom of the will, it will be difficult to different degrees for different persons to exercise their free will as conscience dictates.Moreover, individuals will vary in their psychological capacities to dispose their will to do what conscience dictates. One might retreat further to the plead that all persons evenly can try to dispose their will to do what is right, even up if they will succeed in this enterprise to different degrees. But the ability to try is also a psychological capacity that we should expect would vary empiri chattery across persons. At times Kant seems to appeal to epistemic grounds in reasoning from the neatness of the dear(p) will to the equal worth and dignity of al l human persons.We dont know what allones inner needs are, even our own, so the judgment that some(prenominal)one is firmly disposed to do what is right can never be confirmed. But surely the main issue is whether humans are so ordered that we ought to accord them fundamental equal moral status, not whether, given our beliefs, it is reasonable for us to act as if they are so ordered. The mind that there is a threshold of keen-witted agency capacity much(prenominal)(prenominal)(prenominal) that any being with a capacity preceding(prenominal) the threshold is a person equal in fundamental moral status to all other persons prompts a handle about how to identify this threshold non arbitrarily.It might seem that lone(prenominal) the difference between nil capacity and some capacity would preclude the skeptical doubt that the line set at any demonstrable level of capacity could just as well have been set high or lower. Regarding the proposal to identify any above-zero capacity as qualifying one for personhood, we ideate a being with notwithstanding a glimmer of capacity to descry the good and the right and to dispose its will toward their fulfillment. The difference between none and some might be infinitesimal, after all.However, a threshold need not be razor-thin. Perhaps there is a line below which beings with coherent capacities in this range are clearly not persons and a higher level such that all beings with capacities above this level are definitely persons. Beings with clear-sighted capacities that fall in the plaza range or gray athletic field between these levels are near-persons. The levels can be set sufficiently far apart that the difference between scoring at the lower and the higher levels is undeniably of moral significance.But the difference between the thinking(prenominal) capacities of the beings just above the higher line, withdraw them marginal persons, and the beings at the upper end of the scale who have saintly champion capacities, is not thereby shown to be insignificant. At the lower end we might imagine persons like the villains depicted in the grungy Harry Clint Eastwood movies. These unfortunates are not shown as having moral capacities which they are flouting, but quite an as bad by record, and perhaps not entitled to full human rights.No doubt this is a crass outlook, but the question dust whether the analysis we can offer of the basis for human equality generates a refutation of it. imagine soulfulness asserts that the difference between the noetic agency capacities of the virtually perceptive saints and the most(prenominal) unreflective and animalistic villains defines a difference in fundamental moral status that is just as important for godliness as the difference between the cerebral agency capacities of near-persons and marginal persons. What mistake does this claim embody?COMMENTS ON KANTS estimable THEORY Because we so comm unless take it for granted that moral values a re intimately connected with the goal of human well-being or gaiety, Kants insisting that these two concepts are absolutely mugwump makes it difficult to grasp his point of arrest and well-fixed to misunderstand it. The following comments are intended to help the you to lift the most common misunderstandings and appreciate the sort of outlook that characterizes what Kant takes to be the heart of the honorable life.Kants honourable conjecture is often cited as the paradigm of a deontological theory. Although the theory certainly can be seriously criticized, it remains probably the finest analysis of the bases of the concepts of moral dogma and moral tariff. Kants endeavor to ground moral occupation in the temper of the human being as basi cally a rational being marks him as the last great enlightenment thinker.In spite of the incident that his precise philosophy in epistemology and metaphysics brought an end to The be on of basis, in ethics his attempt to advance the form of any ethical responsibleness from the very nature of a rational being is the philosophical high urine mark of the Enlightenments plenty of humanity as essentially and unambiguously rational.What Kant aims to provide is a metaphysics of morals in the sense of an analysis of the grounds of moral contract in the nature of a rational being. In other lyric, Kant aims to conclude his ethical theory purely by a priori reasoning from the concept of what it is to be a human person as a rational agent.The fact that great deal have the faculty of being able to use reason to decide how to act expresses the fundamental metaphysical pattern -the basis or foundation in the nature of reality- on which Kants ethical theory is erected. Kant begins his treatise, The Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals with the famous hammy sentence Nothing can maybe be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which can be called good without qualification, except a good will. 1. What does Kant look upon by good without qualification? on the face of it community try to seek and vitiate many different sorts of things those things which they seek they call good, while those they try to avoid, they call bad. These goods which people seek may be divided into those which are inclination as doer to some further end and those which they seek as good as ends in themselves. Obviously some things may be good as elbow room to one end and bad as performer to some other end. assorted persons, move by different ends, will and then find different things good and bad ( relative to their different ends).More diet is good to a starving man, but it is bad to one overweight. In order for something to be good without qualification it must not be merely good as blottos to one end but bad as means to some other end. It must be sought as good all independently of serving as a means to something else it must be good in-itself. Furthermore, while one thing may be go od as means relative to a special(a) end, that end becomes a means relative to some other end. So a college diploma may be sought as good as a means for the end of a higher-paying job.And a higher-paying job may be good as a means to increased monetary security and increased financial security may be good as a means to obtaining the necessities of life as well as a few of its luxuries. However, if we seek A precisely for the involvement of B, and B entirely for the sake of C, etc. , because there is never a justification for seeking A at the beginning of such a series unless there is something at the end of that series which we seek as a good in-itself not merely as means to some further end. much(prenominal) an ultimate end would then be an absolute sort of than a relative good. Kant means that a good will is good without qualification as such an absolute good in-itself, universally good in every instance and never merely as good to some yet further end. 2. wherefore is a g ood will the barely thing which is universally absolutely good? Kants point is that to be universally and absolutely good, something must be good in every instance of its occurrence.He argues that all those things which people call good (including intelligence, wit, judgment, courage, resolution, perseverance, power, riches, honor, health, and even delight itself) can become highly bad and mischievous if the will which is to make use of them is not good. In other words, if we imagine a bad person (i. e. one who willed or wanted to do evil), who had all of these so-called goods (intelligence, wit, etc. ), these very traits would make only that much worse his will to do what is wrong.(We would get the culpable master-mind of the comic books. ) Even health often also cited as a good in- itself may serve to make a person insensitive and indifferent to the lack of good health in others. 3. Isnt pleasure such a universal, absolute good in-itself? Kant answers clearly, No. However, many philosophers (the ones we call eudaemonists) have assumed the obvious answer to be Yes. All ancient eudaemonistic ethical theories as well as modern utilitarian theories virtually define felicitousness as the absolute end of all ethical behavior.Such eudaemonistic ethical theories are attractive because of the fact that they make it easy to answer the question Why should I do what is morally right? For any eudaemonistic theory the answer will always be Because the morally right make headway is always ultimately in the amuse of your own happiness. Since these theories generally assume that people really are actuate by a go for for their own happiness, their only problem is to show that the morally right trans exertion really does serve as the best means to obtain the end of happiness.Once you are led to see this, so such theories assume, the question Why should I do what is morally right? is automatically answered. Kant totally rejects this eudaemonistic way of ethic al theorizing he calls decisions made fit to such a calculation of what produces your own happiness prudential decisions and he distinguishes them sharply from ethical decisions. This is not because Kant thinks we are not motivated by a desire for happiness, in fact like the ancient philosophers, he takes it for granted that we are however, such motivation cannot be that which makes an feat ethically right or wrong.The fact that an legal action might lead to happiness cannot be the grounds of moral obligation. Kant regards the notion of happiness as both besides indistinct and too experimental to serve as the grounds for moral obligation why we ought to do something. In the first place it is too indefinite because all people have very different sorts of talents, tastes and enjoyments which mean in effect that one persons happiness may be some other persons misery. This is because the concept is empirical in the sense that the only way you can know whether what you seek will actually serve to bring you happiness is by experience.As Kant points out, it is impossible that the most clear-sighted man should frame to himself a definite conception of what he really wills in this. Since we cannot know a priori onwards an action whether it really will be conducive to our happiness (because the notion is so indefinite that even the most clear-sighted amongst us cannot know everything that must form part of his own happiness) the desire for our own happiness cannot serve as a antecedent to determine our will to do this or that action. Moreover, Kant observes that even the general well-being and delight with ones condition that is called happiness, can inspire pride, and often presumption, if there is not a good will to correct the influence of these on the mind. In other words happiness cannot be good without qualification for if we imagine it occurring in a person totally devoid of the desire to do what is right, it could very well lead to all sorts of imm oral actions. 4. What does Kant mean by a good will? To act out of a good will for Kant means to act out of a sense of moral obligation or vocation.In other words, the moral agent does a circumstance action not because of what it produces (its consequences) in basis of human experience, but because he or she recognizes by reasoning that it is morally the right thing to do and thus regards him or herself as having a moral craft or obligation to do that action. One may of course as an added fact get some pleasure or other gain from doing the right thing, but to act morally, one does not do it for the sake of its desirable consequences, but or else because one understands that it is morally the right thing to do.In this respect Kants descry towards morality parallels the Christians get concerning obedience to Gods commandments, according to which the Christian copys Gods commandments simply because God commands them, not for the sake of rewards in heaven after death or from fea r of punishment in hell. In a similar way, for Kant the rational being does what is morally right because he recognizes himself as having a moral duty to do so kinda than for anything he or she may get out of it. 5. When does one act from a former of doing ones duty?Kant answers that we do our moral duty when our author is determined by a formula recognized by reason rather than the desire for any expected consequence or randy feeling which may cause us to act the way we do. The will is be as that which provides the motives for our actions. Obviously many times we are motivated by specialised desires or emotions. I may act the way I do from a feeling of friendship for a circumstance proposition individual, or from desire for a detail consequence. I may also be motivated by special emotions of fear, or envy, or pity, etc.When I act in these ways, I am motivated by a desire for a particular end in Kants vocabulary I am tell to act out of inclination. Insofar as an action i s motivated by inclination, the motive to do it is contingent upon the desire for the particular end which the action is imagined to produce. Thus as different rational agents might have different inclinations, there is no one motive from inclination common to all rational beings. Kant distinguishes acts motivated by inclination from those through with(p) on prescript.For example someone may ask why I did a certain thing, and point out that it brought me no gain, or perhaps even made life a bit less pleasant to which I might reply, I know I do not stand to gain by this action, but I do it because of the principle of the thing. For Kant, this sort of state of mind is the essence of the moral consciousness. When I act on principle the sole factor determining my motive is that this particular action exemplifies a particular case falling under a general law or maxim. For Kant the mental process by which the actor understands that a particular case move under a certain principle is an exercise in reasoning, or to be more precise, what Kant called hard-nosed reason, reason utilize as a guide to action. ( processed Reason is reason used to attain certainty, or what Kant called scientific knowledge. ) Since to have moral worth an action must be done on principle, and to see that a certain principle applies to a particular action requires the exercise of reason, only rational beings can be said to wear morally. 6. Why does Kant believe that to have moral worth an action must be done on principle rather than inclination?Kants argument here may seem strange to the coetaneous outlook, for it assumes that everything in nature is designed to serve a purpose. Now it is an obvious fact that human beings do have a faculty of serviceable reason, reason utilize to the guidance of actions. (Kant is of course fully sure the people often fail to exercise this faculty i. e. they act non-rationally (without reason) or even irrationally (against what reason dictates) but h e intends that his ethical theory is normative, prescribing how people ought to give birth, rather than descriptive of how they actually do lead.)If everything in nature serves some purpose then the faculty of practical reason must have some purpose. Kant argues that this purpose cannot be merely the proficiency of some special(prenominal) craved end, or even the attainment of happiness in general, for if it were, it would have been far better for nature simply to have endowed persons with an instinct to achieve this end, as is the case with the non- rational animals. Therefore, the fact that human beings have a faculty of practical reason cannot be explained by claiming that it allows them to attain some particular end.So the fact that reason can guide our actions, but cannot do so for the sake of achieving some desired end, leads Kant to the decisiveness that the function of practical reason must be to allow humans as rational beings to apply general principles to particular i nstances of action, or in other words to engage in moral reasoning as a way of determining ones moral obligation what is the right action to do. Thus we act morally only when we act rationally to apply a moral principle to determine the motive of our action. 7. Do all persons have the self very(prenominal)(prenominal) moral duties? According to Kant only rational beings can be said to act morally.Reason for Kant (as for all the Enlightenment thinkers) is the kindred for all persons in other words there isnt a curt mans reason versus a rich mans reason or a white mans reason versus a stern mans reason. All persons are equal as potentially rational beings. Therefore, if reason dictates that one person, in a particular topographic point, has a moral duty to do a particular thing, then any person, in that same item, would equally well have a duty to do that same thing. In this sense Kants reasoning parallels the way in which stoicism led Roman lawyers to the conclusion that all citizens are equal before the law.Thus Kant is a moral absolutist in the sense that all persons have the same moral duties, for all persons are equal as rational beings. But this one-man rule does not mean that Kant holds that our moral duties are not relative to the situation in which we find ourselves. Thus it is quite possible for Kant to conclude that in one particular situation I may have a duty to remain my promise, but in another situation (in which, for example, keeping a promise conflicts with a higher duty) I may equally well be morally have to break a promise. 8.Why is it that actions done for the sake of some end cannot have moral worth? Since what ones moral duties are in a particular situation are the same for all persons, ones moral duties must be independent of the particular likes and dislikes of the moral agent. Now any action which is motivated by the desire for some particular end presupposes that the agent has the desire for that end. However, from the simpl e concept of a rational being it is not possible to deduce that any particular rational being would have any particular desired ends.Most people, of course, desire to seek pleasure and avoid pain, but there is no logical contradiction involved in the notion of a rational being who does not desire pleasure or perhaps who desires pain. Thus reason does not dictate that any particular rational being has any particular end. But if the desire for a particular end gave an action its moral worth, then only those rational beings who happened in fact to desire that end would regard such actions as good, while those that desired to avoid such an end, would regard the action as bad. (Thus for example eudaemonistic theories which assume the end of achieving happiness is what gives an action its moral value, would serve to induce only those beings who happened to have the desire for happiness to behave morally. For those rational beings who happened to desire to avoid happiness, there would be n o incentive to behave morally and what searchs good to the happiness-seeker will appear positively bad to one who seeks to avoid happiness. ) But, as we have seen above, Kants absolutism reaches the conclusion that moral obligation is the same for all persons.Thus the ground of moral obligation, what makes an action a moral duty, cannot lie in the end which that act produces. 9. What does reason tell us about the principle that determines the morally dutiful motive? Since Kant has govern out the ends (i. e. the consequences) which an act produces as well as any motive but those determined by the application of principle as determining moral duty, he is faced now with the task of deriving the fundamental principles of his ethical theory simply from the concept of what it is to be a rational being.He now argues (in a very obscure manner) that from this notion of what is demanded by being rational, he can deduce that it would be irrational to act on any principle which would not appl y equally to any other actor in the same situation. In other words, Kant claims that reason dictates that the act we are morally oblige to do is one which is motivated by adherence to a principle which could, without inconsistency, be held to apply to any (and all) rational agents.This fundamental ethical principle, which is commonly called The Categorical Imperative, Kant summarizes with the direction that I am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim become a universal law. Kants claim that Reason demands the moral agent to act on a universal law thus in many ways parallels saviour dictum that God commands that those who love Him obey The Golden Rule. 10. What is a categorical imperative? Any parameter of moral obligation which I make the principle of my action (my maxim in Kants vocabulary), in the context of a particularised situation, constitutes an imperative. I might, in such a situation, choose to act on a statement of the form, If I desire some specific end (e. g. happiness, maximum pleasure, power, etc. ), then I ought to do such and such an action. In doing so I would be acting on what Kant calls a suppositious imperative. However, Kant has already ruled out ends as the grounds for moral obligation thus hypothetical imperatives cannot serve as the basis for determining my moral duty. However, if I act on a principle which has the form, In circumstances of such and such a character, I ought to.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.